Skip to main content
Log in

From Wendt to Kuhn: Reviving the ‘Third Debate’ in International Relations

  • Another ‘Great Debate’ in IR?
  • Published:
International Politics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Constructivism is often identified as the legitimate occupant of the middle ground between rationalism and reflectivism that emerged from the Third Debate in international relations (IR) theory. Indeed, the rationalist–constructivist debate is already being framed as the next dominant debate with the IR community. This paper evaluates the bridge-building project as initiated by Alexander Wendt, and takes issue with the via media as proposed by the so-called conventional constructivists. It is claimed that the rationalist–constructivist debate has been limited to a discussion of ontology, which has brought about a contradiction between ontology and epistemology. Returning to the pressing epistemological issues that were put on the table by reflectivist scholars, this article refocuses the current debate by taking up the Kuhnian link between substance and science. It elaborates a view of science as a communal practice built on intersubjective conventions and argumentative procedures. This leads to an alternative conception of the middle ground as a communicative space.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Figure 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Fifth Pan-European International Relations Conference ‘Constructing World Orders’ of the ECPR/SGIR The Hague, September 9–11, 2004.

  2. See also Checkel (1997), Finnemore and Sikkink (1998, 2001), Jupille et al. (2003), Risse (2002), and Sterling-Folker (2002). For a genuine debate between constructivism and rationalism, and an elaboration of a constructivist research program in positivist terms, see Checkel and Moravcsik (2001).

  3. For typologies of different types of constructivism, see for instance Katzenstein et al. (1998), Adler (1997), Hopf (1998), Ruggie (1998).

  4. Especially poststructuralists have questioned the idea of epistemology as rules on how to produce secure, let alone objective, knowledge (cf. Wæver, 1997, 16–17). Also, for them the ontological does not refer so much to ‘what is’ but is invoked mainly as a way of criticizing the onto-political (see e.g. Campbell, 1998; Edkins and Pin-Fat, 1999). However, even if the concern is with the onto-political (the way central ontological categories such as sovereignty or the state are politically constructed), it is still necessary to document carefully the dominant discourses through which the onto-political is produced, resisted and reified. In other words, poststructuralists too cannot escape the question of what constitutes good research in the examination of the onto-political (see Price and Reus-Smit, 1998; Milliken, 1999). See also the fourth section.

  5. Mervyn Frost (1986), Towards a Normative Theory of International Relations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; quoted by George and Campbell (1990). Lapid makes a similar remark when he talks about the tragedy of international relations, as ‘they proved incapable of either fruitfully adopting or decisively rejecting the grail of positivist science’ (Lapid, 1989, 246).

  6. This was also the point of contention in the so-called Second Debate between traditionalist/historians and behavioralists/scientists (cf. Schmidt, 2002). However, this ‘history vs science’ controversy did not really disturb the safe grounds of positivist epistemology, and focused on methodological issues instead (cf. Lapid, 1989). In this account, Wæver's (1996) explicit distinction between the interparadigm debate and the more philosophical debate between rationalists and reflectivists has indeed been useful to draw attention to the latter. Nevertheless, it risks a too clear separation of substance and science. This issue is pursued below.

  7. The strategy to reduce reflectivism to idealism and to reject it on those terms has been repeatedly deployed by IR theorists (see Mearsheimer, 1995; Østerud, 1996; Wight, 1999). On the difference between reflectivism and idealism, see Laclau and Mouffe (1990).

  8. Keohane (1988, 382) reproached reflectivist scholars for leading the discipline into a ‘debate at the purely theoretical level,’ which distracts researchers from the subject matter, world politics, in favor of a ‘programmatically diversionary philosophical discussion.’

  9. It should be noted that whereas Lapid equals the rationalist/reflectivist debate with positivism vs post-positivism, the ‘dissident agenda’ entails more than a post-positivist stance. George and Campbell (1990, 270) identify the following interdisciplinary elements of critical analysis: (i) inadequacy of positivist/empiricist approaches to knowledge; (ii) focus on actual process of knowledge construction in repudiating external sources of understanding (i.e. Archimedean points); (iii) focus on linguistic construction of reality; (iv) focus on question of subjectivity, that is, construction of meaning and identity.

  10. See Wendt (1992) for a first contribution to the bridge-building project, but notably Wendt (1999) for a full-fledged articulation of a social theory to international politics.

  11. For a detailed discussion of the uneasy tensions of structure/agency, and in particular of mental causality and rump materialism in ‘middle-ground’ constructivism see also Kessler (2007).

  12. In turn this makes it virtually impossible to theorize change (which was one of the original promises of constructivism and its main critique against neo-realism, see e.g. Wendt, 1992). Moreover, such a reading of norms ignores another of Wendt's premises, that is, the need to move beyond the level of behavior and take effects on identity and, ultimately, interests into account (see e.g. Wendt, 1999). Finally, it ignores Kratochwil and Ruggie's (1986, 767) famous critique that it is problematic to conceive of norms as causes, because they are counterfactually valid.

  13. The resort to cognitive psychology is advocated by Checkel (1998, 2001a). See also Johnston (2001). To understand how socialization works, many constructivists study arguing dynamics, focusing on the role of persuasion, deliberation, shaming and rhetorical action (see, among others, Risse et al., 1999; Risse, 2000; Checkel, 2001b; Schimmelfennig, 2001). Although substantial differences exist among them, most authors — drawing upon laboratory-like, non-contextual experiments of communication — go on to specify the conditions under which actors are more likely to persuade other actors of the appropriateness of new norms. The question is, however, whether socialization can be ‘measured’ accurately if one only focuses upon arguing dynamics as such, hence ignoring issues of embeddedness in broader discursive frameworks. Kessler (2007), in this regard, distinguishes between ‘thin’ and ‘thick intersubjectivity.’

  14. See also a recent exchange between Friedrich Kratochwil (2007a, 2007b) and Colin Wight (2007a, 2007b) on these issues.

  15. This parallels Poppers later conception of the scientific community as ‘a set of persons who share certain techniques such as measurement procedures, methodological commitments and presumptions of what constitutes “good practice” in a given field’ (Karl Popper (1972), Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, Oxford University Press; quoted by Lebow, 2007, 17).

  16. In distinction to societas, Oakeshott refers to universitas as a mode of association that postulates the idea of a substantive or common purpose. This is the type of association characteristic for Kuhn's paradigmatic community which pursues a set of common goals, hence enjoying relatively full communication and unanimous professional judgement (Kuhn, 1970: 176–178).

  17. For a similar analogy, see Hermann (1998) who compares different approaches to distinct kind of grammatical structures and IR to the Tower of Babel. See also Guzzini (2001).

  18. In terms of engagement and open dialogue between opposing perspectives, a recent exemplar is Checkel and Moravcsik's (2001) forum about constructivism vs rationalism in European Union Politics. A similar endeavor was undertaken by Fierke and Nicholson (2001) in their conversation on the notion of games from a linguistic, respectively rational choice perspective. However, as discussed above, we take issue with the emphasis on synthesis, which seems to be the aim in both cases.

  19. Kratochwil (2000, 92) argues that Popper's stance in his later work does not differ that much from Kuhn's. In The Myth of the Framework Popper argues the virtue of disagreement, where communication does not depend on a shared (theoretical) framework, but rather on the respect of certain ethical principles. See also Lebow (2007).

  20. This has also been the stake of a recent debate on the merits of a pragmatic approach to theory building, as proposed by Kratochwil (2007b) in his Tartu lecture. See the special issue of the Journal of International Relations and Development 10(1): 2007.

  21. For instance, Foucault remarks that ‘those texts that we now would call scientific — those dealing with cosmology and the heavens, medicine and illnesses, natural sciences and geography — were accepted in the Middle Ages, and accepted as “true”, only when marked with the name of their author. “Hippocrates said”, “Plinty recounts”, were not really formulas of an argument based on authority; they were the markers inserted in discourses that were supported to be received as statements of demonstrated truth’ (Foucault, 1991, 109).

  22. In The Essential Tension Kuhn (1977, 322) lists five indicative criteria that partly overlap: ‘accuracy, consistency, scope, simplicity, and fruitfulness.’ Whereas these count as a set of values to guide and shape theory development, these criteria are rather imprecise on their own terms — which is the(ir) very point: ‘What the tradition sees as eliminable imperfections in its rules of choice I take to be in part responses to the essential nature of science’ (Kuhn, 1977, 330). In other words, this only illuminates the social character of the scientific endeavor — because scientists may differ about the relative weight of the criteria, and for instance their application to concrete cases, science is not a determinate process dictated by ‘rational, unanimous choice’ and a given formula (Kuhn, 1977, 326, quoted by Suganami, 2007, 31). The discussion about ‘scientific’ criteria is as much part of the academic endeavor ‘of our making’ as the substance of particular research projects themselves.

  23. This includes conventions with regard to citations, footnotes and bibliographies (see also note 21).

  24. For instance, the operationalization of mutual constitution of much conventional constructivist work is problematic in this regard. While these scholars are to be praised for their efforts to deal with the structure/agency problem in empirical research, the proposed solution of ‘bracketing’ so far does not seem very satisfying for it ends up measuring the impact of structure upon agents on the one hand, and the impact of agents on structure, but cannot grasp the dynamic of mutual constitution. This is even more problematic in case of those studies that add a temporal dimension to the analysis. Alternatively, such analyses result in privileging the agent over the structure, or vice versa.

  25. Pollins (2007, 93–94) usefully distinguishes between falsifiability and falsificationism. Whereas he rejects the latter because of its positivist overtones, he embraces the ideal of falsifiability. Falsifiability can be defined simply, as King et al. (1994, 19) do, as ‘the principle that theories should be stated clearly enough so that they could be wrong.’

  26. To a certain extent this possibility is reflected in how we teach students about the historiography of our discipline. Being detached to the enmities of the debates, they are often encouraged to put on different hats in order to give specific theories their best shot, and dissect internal inconsistencies at the same time. On parochialism in teaching, see Alker and Biersteker (1984).

References

  • Adler, E. (1997) ‘Seizing the Middle Ground: Constructivism in World Politics’, European Journal of International Relations 3 (3): 319–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adler, E. (2002) ‘Constructivism and International Relations’, in W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse and B.A. Simmons (eds.) Handbook of International Relations, London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alker, H.R. and Biersteker, T. (1984) ‘The Dialectics of World Order: Notes for a Future Archeologist of International Savoir Faire’, International Studies Quarterly 28 (2): 121–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashley, R.K. and Walker, R.B.J. (1990) ‘Introduction: Speaking the Language of Exile: Dissident Thought in International Studies’, International Studies Quarterly 34 (3): 259–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ba, A. and Hoffman, M.J. (2003) ‘Making and Remaking the World for IR 101: A Resource for Teaching Social Constructivism in Introductory Classes’, International Studies Perspectives 4 (1): 15–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnett, M. and Finnemore, M. (1999) ‘The Politics, Power and Pathologies of International Organizations’, International Organization 53 (4): 705–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. (1998) National Deconstruction: Violence, Identity, and Justice in Bosnia, Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Checkel, J.T. (1997) ‘International Norms and Domestic Politics: Bridging the Rationalist-Constructivist Divide’, European Journal of International Relations 3 (4): 473–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Checkel, J.T. (1998) ‘The Constructivist Turn in International Relations Theory’, World Politics 50 (1): 324–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Checkel, J.T. (2001a) ‘Taking Deliberation Seriously’, ARENA Working Paper no. 14, ARENA/University of Oslo, Oslo.

  • Checkel, J.T. (2001b) ‘Why Comply? Social Learning and European Identity Change’, International Organization 55 (3): 553–588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Checkel, J.T. and Moravcsik, A. (2001) ‘A Constructivist Research Program in EU Studies? (Forum Section)’, European Union Politics 2 (2): 219–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edkins, J. and Pin-Fat, V. (1999) ‘The Subject of the Political’, in J. Edkins, N. Persram and V. Pin-Fat (eds.) Sovereignty and Subjectivity, Boulder: Lynne Rienner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fearon, J. and Wendt, A. (2002) ‘Rationalism v. Constructivism: A Skeptical View’, in W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse and B.A. Simmons (eds.) Handbook of International Relations, London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fierke, K.M. (2001) ‘Critical Methodology and Constructivism’, in K.M. Fierke and K.E. Jørgensen (eds.) Constructing International Relations: The Next Generation, London: M.E. Sharpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fierke, K.M. (2002) ‘Links Across the Abyss: Language and Logic in International Relations’, International Studies Quarterly 46 (3): 331–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fierke, K.M. and Jørgensen, K.E. (2001) ‘Introduction’, in K.M. Fierke and K.E. Jørgensen (eds.) Constructing International Relations. The Next Generation, New York: M.E. Sharpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fierke, K.M. and Nicholson, M. (2001) ‘Divided by a Common Language: Formal and Constructivist Approaches to Games’, Global Society 15 (1): 7–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finnemore, M. (1996) National Interests in International Society, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnemore, M. and Sikkink, K. (1998) ‘International Norm Dynamics and Political Change’, International Organization 52 (4): 887–917.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finnemore, M. and Sikkink, K. (2001) ‘Taking Stock: The Constructivist Research Program in International Relations and Comparative Politics’, Annual Review of Political Science 4: 391–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1991) ‘What is an Author?’, in P. Rabinow (ed.) The Foucault Reader, London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • George, J. and Campbell, D. (1990) ‘Patterns of Dissent and the Celebration of Difference: Critical Social Theory and International Relations’, International Studies Quarterly 34 (3): 269–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, J. and Keohane, R.O. (eds.) (1993) Ideas and Foreign Policy: Beliefs, Institutions, and Political Change, Ithaca: Cornell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guzzini, S. (2000) ‘A Reconstruction of Constructivism in International Relations’, European Journal of International Relations 6 (2): 147–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guzzini, S. (2001) ‘The Significance and Roles of Teaching Theory in International Relations’, Journal of International Relations and Development 4 (2): 98–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, F. and Cobb, J. (2003) ‘Multiple Dialogues, Layered Syntheses, and the Limits of Expansive Cumulation’, International Studies Review 5 (1): 144–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hermann, M.G. (1998) ‘One Field, Many Perspectives: Building the Foundations for Dialogue’, International Studies Quarterly 42 (4): 605–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopf, T. (1998) ‘The Promise of Constructivism in International Theory’, International Security 23 (1): 171–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopf, T. (2007) ‘The Limits of Interpreting Evidence’, in R.N. Lebow and M. Lichbach (eds.) Theory and Evidence in Comparative Politics and International Relations, Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jepperson, R.L., Wendt, A . and Katzenstein, P.J . (1996) ‘Norms, Identity, and Culture in National Security’, in P.J. Katzenstein (ed.) The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, A.I. (2001) ‘Treating International Institutions as Social Environments’, International Studies Quarterly 45 (4): 487–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jupille, J., Caporaso, J.A . and Checkel, J.T. (2003) ‘Integrating Institutions. Theory, Method, and the Study of the European Union’, Comparative Political Studies 36 (1): 7–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katzenstein, P.J., Keohane, R.O . and Krasner, S.D. (1998) ‘International Organization and the Study of World Politics’, International Organization 52 (4): 645–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keohane, R.O. (1988) ‘International Institutions: Two Approaches’, International Studies Quarterly 32 (4): 379–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kessler, O. (2007) ‘From Agents and Structures to Minds and Bodies: Of Supervenience, Quantum, and the Linguistic Turn’, Journal of International Relations and Development 10 (3): 243–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, G., Keohane, R.O. and Verba, S. (1994) Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klotz, A. (2001) ‘Can We Speak a Common Constructivist Language?’, in K.M. Fierke and K.E. Jørgensen (eds.) Constructing International Relations: The Next Generation, London: M.E. Sharpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratochwil, F. (2000) ‘Constructing a New Orthodoxy? Wendt's ‘Social Theory of International Politics’ and the Constructivist Challenge’, Millennium 29 (1): 73–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratochwil, F. (2003) ‘The Monologue of “Science”’, International Studies Review 5 (1): 124–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratochwil, F. and Ruggie, J.G. (1986) ‘International Organization: A State of the Art on an Art of the State’, International Organization 40 (4): 753–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratochwil, F.V. (2007a) ‘Of Communities, Gangs, Historicity and the Problem of Santa Claus: Replies to my Critics’, Journal of International Relations and Development 10 (1): 57–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratochwil, F.V. (2007b) ‘Of False Promises and Good Bets: a Pleas for a Pragmatic Approach to Theory Building (the Tartu Lecture)’, Journal of International Relations and Development 10 (1): 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. (1977) The Essential Tension, Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laclau, E. and Mouffe, C. (1985) Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics, London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laclau, E. and Mouffe, C. (1990) ‘Post-Marxism Without Apologies’, in E. Laclau (ed.) New Reflections on the Revolution of Our Time, London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lapid, Y. (1989) ‘The Third Debate: On the Prospects of International Theory in a Post-Positivist Era’, International Studies Quarterly 33: 235–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lapid, Y. (2003) ‘Through Dialogue to Engaged Pluralism: The Unfinished Business of the Third Debate’, International Studies Review 5 (1): 128–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lebow, R.N. (2007) ‘Social Science as an Ethical Practice’, Journal of International Relations and Development 10 (1): 16–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maghroori, R. and Ramberg, B. (eds.) (1982) Globalism versus Realism: International Relations’ Third Debate, Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mearsheimer, J.J. (1995) ‘The False Promises of International Institutions’, International Security 19 (3): 5–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milliken, J. (1999) ‘The Study of Discourse in International Relations: A Critique of Research and Methods’, European Journal of International Relations 5 (2): 225–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moravscik, A. (2003) ‘Theory Synthesis in International Relations: Real Not Metaphysical’, International Studies Review 5 (1): 131–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oakeshott, M. (1975) On Human Conduct, Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onuf, N.G. (1989) World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social Theory and International Relations, Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Østerud, Ø (1996) ‘Antinomies of Postmodernism in International Studies’, Journal of Peace Research 33 (4): 385–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patomäki, H. and Wight, C. (2000) ‘After Postpositivism? The Promises of Critical Realism’, International Studies Quarterly 44: 213–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennings, P., Keman, H . and Kleinnijenhuis, J . (1999) Doing Research in Political Science. An Introduction to Comparative Methods and Statitiscs, London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollins, B.M. (2007) ‘Beyond Logical Positivism: Reframing King, Keohane and Verba's Designing Social Inquiry’, in R.N. Lebow and M. Lichbach (eds.) Theory and Evidence in Comparative Politics and International Relations, Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, R. and Reus-Smit, C. (1998) ‘Dangerous Liaisons? Critical International Theory and Constructivism’, European Journal of International Relations 4 (3): 259–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Puchala, D.J. (2000) ‘Marking a Weberian Moment: Our Discipline Looks Ahead’, International Studies Perspectives 1: 133–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reus-Smit, C. (2001) ‘Constructivism’, in S. Burchill, Linklater, A, Devetak, R, Donnelly, J, Paterson, M, Reus-Smit, C. and True, J. (eds.) Theories of International Relations, Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risse, T. (2000) ‘“Let's Argue!” Communicative Action in World Politics’, International Organization 54 (1): 1–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Risse, T. (2002) ‘Constructivism and International Institutions: Toward Conversations across Paradigms’, in I. Katznelson and H.V. Milner (eds.) Polticial Science. State of the Discipline, New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Risse, T., Ropp, S.C. and Sikkink, K . (1999) The Power of Human Rights: International Norms and Domestic Change, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1980) Philosophy and the Mirror of Language, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (1987) Knowledge and Power: Toward a Political Philosophy of Science, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruggie, J.G. (1998) ‘What Makes the World Hang Together? Neo-utilitarianism and the Social Constructivist Challenge’, International Organization 52 (4): 855–885.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schimmelfennig, F. (2001) ‘The Community Trap: Liberal Norms, Rhetorical Action and the Eastern Enlargement of the European Union’, International Organization 55 (1): 47–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, B.C. (2002) ‘On the History and Historiography of International Relations’, in W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse and B.A. Simmons (eds.) Handbook of International Relations, London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. (1995) The Construction of Social Reality, New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapcott, R. (2001) Justice, Community, and Dialogue in International Relations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, S. (1996) ‘Positivism and Beyond’, in S. Smith, K. Booth, and M. Zalewski (eds.) International Theory: Positivism and Beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, S. (2001) ‘Reflectivist and Constructivist Approaches to International Theory’, in J. Baylis and S. Smith (eds.) The Globalization of World Politics: an Introduction to International Relations, 2nd edn, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, S. (2002) ‘Alternative and Critical Perspectives’, in F.P. Harvey and M. Brecher (eds.) Millennial Reflections on International Studies, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, S. (2003) ‘Dialogue and the Reinforcement of Orthodoxy in International Relations’, International Studies Review 5 (1): 141–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterling-Folker, J. (2002) ‘Realism and the Constructivist Challenge: Rejecting, Reconstructing, or Rereading’, International Studies Review 4 (1): 73–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stokes, G. (1998) Popper. Philosophy, Politics and Scientific Method, Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suganami, H. (2007) ‘Friedrich Kratochwil's Pragmatic Search for a Theory of International Relations’, Journal of International Relations and Development 10 (1): 25–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wæver, O. (1996) ‘The Rise and Fall of the Inter-paradigm Debate’, in S. Smith, K. Booth, and M. Zalewski (eds.) International Theory: Positivism and Beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wæver, O. (1997) ‘Figures of International Thought: Introducing Persons instead of Paradigms’, in I.B. Neumann and O. Wæver (eds.) The Future of International Relations. Masters in the Making?, London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R.B.J. (1989) ‘History and Structure in the Theory of International Relations’, Millennium 18 (2): 163–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walt, S.M. (1998) ‘International Relations: One World, Many Theories’, Foreign Policy 110: 29–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, A. (1987) ‘The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory’, International Organization 41 (3): 335–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, A. (1992) ‘Anarchy is What States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics’, International Organization 46 (2): 391–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, A. (1999) A Social Theory of International Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, A. (2000) ‘On the Via Media: A Response to the Critics’, Review of International Studies 26 (1): 165–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wight, C. (1999) ‘Metacampbell: The Epistemological Problematics of Perspectivism’, Review of International Studies 25 (2): 311–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wight, C. (2002) ‘Philosophy of Social Science and International Relations’, in W. Carlsnaes, T. Risse and B.A. Simmons (eds.) Handbook of International Relations, London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wight, C. (2007a) ‘Inside the Epistemological Cave All Bets are Off’, Journal of International Relations and Development 10 (1): 40–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wight, C. (2007b) ‘A Response to Friedrich Kratochwil: Why Shooting the Messenger Does Not Make the Bad News Go Away!’, Journal of International Relations and Development 10 (3): 301–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zehfuss, M. (2002) Constructivism in International Relations: The Politics of Reality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Aalberts, T., van Munster, R. From Wendt to Kuhn: Reviving the ‘Third Debate’ in International Relations. Int Polit 45, 720–746 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1057/ip.2008.26

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/ip.2008.26

Keywords

Navigation